Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Clinical intuition versus statistics: different modes of tacit knowledge in clinical epidemiology and evidence-based medicine

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Despite its phenomenal success since its inception in the early nineteen-nineties, the evidence-based medicine movement has not succeeded in shaking off an epistemological critique derived from the experiential or tacit dimensions of clinical reasoning about particular individuals. This critique claims that the evidence-based medicine model does not take account of tacit knowing as developed by the philosopher Michael Polanyi. However, the epistemology of evidence-based medicine is premised on the elimination of the tacit dimension from clinical judgment. This is demonstrated through analyzing the dichotomy between clinical and statistical intuition in evidence-based medicine’s epistemology of clinical reasoning. I argue that clinical epidemiology presents a more nuanced epistemological model for the application of statistical epidemiology to the clinical context. Polanyi’s theory of tacit knowing is compatible with the model of clinical reasoning associated with clinical epidemiology, but not evidence-based medicine.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Often, Polanyi’s tacit knowing is referred to as tacit knowledge. While these two terms are synonymous, Stephen Henry, who provided useful comments on this paper, has pointed out to me that Polanyi referred to tacit knowing rather than tacit knowledge. Knowing as opposed to knowledge is a more fluid term emphasizing the fluid nature of human cognition.

  2. Polanyi refers to intuition in his major work, Personal Knowledge [5]. He also deals explicitly with intuition in his essay on intuition in scientific reasoning, “Creative Imagination” [6], and Science, Faith and Society [7]. Polanyi does not argue for the traditional philosophical conception of intuition as incorrigible certainty, but as an element of practical reasoning. While intuition covers over hidden logical associations, this does not preclude, but rather requires that we spend time trying to ascertain the tacit elements of scientific reasoning. Clinical intuition as used in this paper shares this meaning with Polanyi’s notion of practical intuition. As such, it must be distinguished from philosophical intuition, for example Kantian intuition, as well as the feminist literature around intuition as a kind of sixth sense. Polanyi’s theory of tacit knowing will be elucidated in more detail towards the conclusion of this paper.

  3. Tim Thornton in a recent article has argued that incorporating tacit knowledge into its epistemology would provide the unifying factor in evidence-based medicine and clinical judgment [8]. Through an appeal to tacit knowledge, Thornton intends to unify the tripartite division of evidence-based medicine, i.e., the integration of research evidence with clinical expertise and patient values. Thornton claims that incorporation of tacit knowledge into its paradigm would undermine the view of evidence-based medicine as algorithmic, or more pejoratively a form of “cookbook medicine.” In another article, David Smith attempts to find the balance between evidence-based medicine and Polanyi’s theory of tacit knowing [9]. Smith criticizes those who attempt to displace evidence-based medicine by tacit knowing. Yet, as argued in this paper, the epistemological issue is not in favoring either tacit knowing or statistical epidemiology, but in mediating between the two, a process which is better accounted for through clinical epidemiology than evidence-based medicine.

  4. Even though there have been developments in evidence-based medicine since Sackett, this paper concentrates on Sackett’s contribution since he laid the intellectual foundations for the movement, which as far as I am aware have not been superseded.

  5. Sackett refers to the evidence-based medicine approach as deductive or hypothetico-deductive. He appropriates this scheme from Peter Medawar’s 1969 study, Induction and Intuition in Scientific Thought [13]

  6. Decision analysis, for its part, refers to the statistical evaluation of the process of cognition of decision-making. Clinical decision analysis refers to the application of statistical methods to evaluate the cognitive processes of decision-making in medicine. Because it deals with cognitive processes of clinical judgment, clinical decision analysis is better suited than evidence-based medicine for incorporating tacit knowing, yet it is also characterized by the perspective that sees everyday decision making as statistically error-prone.

  7. Fisher’s discovery of randomization was an extension of the discovery of correlation discovered by Francis Galton (1822–1911) and refined by Karl Pearson (1857–1936).

  8. For a comparison of Fisher and Bradford Hill, see the series of papers published in the International Journal of Epidemiology (2003) 32: 922–948.

  9. While Bradford Hill did not articulate how this would work, the problem is one of combining statistical data with tacit knowing pertaining to individuals. At the very least Bradford Hill identified the problem of applying statistical data to individual contexts, even though he did not provide a detailed solution to this conundrum.

  10. He is also somewhat infamously remembered for his opposition to the first statistical study authored by Richard Doll and Bradford Hill unequivocally associating lung cancer with smoking.

  11. Fisher’s concept of specifying rigorous uncertainty is comparable with the Viennese philosopher Karl Popper’s famous theory of falsifiability.

  12. While Feinstein was concerned at improving quantitative analysis of clinical data, his approach is also amenable for qualitative investigations.

  13. The uncritical reliance on randomized controlled trials has come under increased scrutiny during the last few years. For another critique of evidence-based medicine’s reliance on randomized controlled trials, see Sleigh [23], Kaptchuk [24], Altman [25], and Grossman [26].

  14. For a more complete description of the influence on and relation between Feinstein and Sackett and the discipline of clinical epidemiology, see the discussion by Jeanne Daly [30], especially chapters two and three, upon which this present analysis is very dependent.

  15. Besides Clinical Judgment [33], notable publications of Feinstein’s include: [3440].

  16. Feinstein’s sense of clinical intuition should not be confused with Kantian philosophical a priori intuitions.

  17. Wilensky’s approach to mathematical education is to allow the learner to make connections between the micro-rules of probability and the resultant macro-statistical distributions as a therapy for “epistemological anxiety” in understanding statistics [43].

References

  1. Polychronis, A., A. Miles, and P. Bentley. 1996. Evidence-based medicine: Reference? Dogma? Neologism? New orthodoxy? Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 2 (1): 1–3.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Feinstein, A.R., and R. Horwitz. 1997. Problems in the ‘evidence’ of ‘evidence-based medicine’. American Journal of Medicine 103 (6): 529–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Malterud, K. 2002. Reflexivity and metapositions: Strategies for appraisal of clinical evidence. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 8 (2): 121–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Henry, S. 2006. Recognizing tacit knowledge in medical epistemology. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 27 (3): 187–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Polanyi, M. 1974. Personal knowledge: Towards a post-critical philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Polanyi, M. 1997. Creative imagination. In In society, economics & philosophy: Selected papers of Michael Polanyi, ed. R.T. Allen, 249–266. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Polanyi, M. 1946. Science, faith and society. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Thornton, T. 2006. Tacit knowledge as the unifying factor in evidence-based medicine and clinical judgment. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 1 (2). http://www.peh-med.com/content/1/1/2. Accessed 25 Mar 2009.

  9. Smith, D.G. 2008. Viewpoint: Envisioning the successful integration of EBM and humanism in the clinical encounter: Fantasy or fallacy. Academic Medicine 83 (3): 268–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Sackett, D.L., W. Scott Richardson, W. Rosenberg, and R. Brian Haynes. 1997. Evidence-based medicine: How to practice and teach EBM. Churchill: Livingstone.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Guyatt, G., and D. Rennie. 2002. The philosophy of evidence-based medicine. User’s guide to the medical literature: A manual for evidence-based clinical practice. Chicago: AMA Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Sackett, D.L., R.B. Haynes, G.H. Guyatt, and P. Tugwell. 1991. Clinical epidemiology: A basic science for clinical medicine. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Medawar, P.B. 1969. Induction and intuition in scientific thought. Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Elstein, A.S. 2000. Clinical problem solving and decision psychology. Academic Medicine 75 (10 Supplement): S134–S136.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Fisher, R. 1926. The arrangement of field experiments. Journal of the Ministry of Agriculture of Great Britain 33: 503–513.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Fisher, R. 1951/1935. The design of experiments. Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd.

  17. Hill, A.B. 1951. The clinical trial. British Medical Bulletin 7: 27882.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Hill, A.B. 1952. The clinical trial. New England Journal of Medicine 247: 113–119.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Hill, A.B. 1990. Memories of the British streptomycin trial in tuberculosis: The first randomized clinical trial. Controlled Clinical Trials 11: 77–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Horton, R. 2000. Common sense and figures: The rhetoric of validity in medicine. Statistics in Medicine 19: 3149–3164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Hill, A.B. 1971. Principles of medical statistics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Marks, H.M. 2003. Rigorous uncertainty: Why R.A. Fisher is important. International Journal of Epidemiology 32: 932–937.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Sleigh, J.W. 1997. Logical limits of randomized controlled trials. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 3 (2): 145–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Kaptchuk, T. 2001. The double-blind, randomized, placebo-controlled trial: Gold standard or golden calf? Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 54: 541–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Altman, D.G. 2000. Statistics in medical journals: Some recent trends. Statistics in Medicine 19: 3281–3284.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Grossman, J., and F. Mackenzie. 2005. The randomized controlled trial: Gold standard, or merely standard? Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 48 (4): 516–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Davidoff, E. 1999. In the teeth of the evidence: The curious use of evidence-based medicine. Mount Sinai Journal of Medicine 66 (2): 75–83.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Guyatt, G.H., D. Sackett, D.W. Taylor, J. Chong, R. Roberts, and S. Pugsley. 1986. Determining optimal therapy: Randomized trials in individual patients. New England Journal of Medicine 314 (14): 889–892.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Paul, J. 1938. Clinical epidemiology. Journal of Clinical Investigation 17: 539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Daly, J. 2005. Evidence-based medicine and the search for a science of clinical care. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Feinstein, A.R. 1973. An analysis of diagnostic reasoning: II. The strategy of intermediate decisions. Yale Journal of Biology and Medicine 46: 264–283.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Evidence.Based.Medicine.Working. Group. 1992. Evidence based medicine: A new approach to the teaching of medicine. JAMA 268: 2420–2425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Feinstein, A.R. 1967. Clinical judgment. Baltimore, Maryland: Williams Wilkins.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Feinstein, A.R. 1963. The basic elements of clinical science. Journal of Chronic Diseases 16: 1125–1133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Feinstein, A.R. 1964. Scientific methodology in clinical medicine: I–III. Annals of Internal Medicine 61 (3, 4, 6): 564–579, 757–781, 1162–1193.

  36. Feinstein, A.R. 1968. Clinical epidemiology: I–III. Annals of Internal Medicine 69 (4, 5, 6): 807–820, 1037–1061, 1287–1311.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Feinstein, A.R. 1977. Clinical biostatistics. C.V. Mosby: Saint Louis.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Feinstein, A.R. 1983. An additional basic science for clinical medicine. Pts. I–III. Annals of Internal Medicine 99: 393–397, 544–550, 705–712.

  39. Feinstein, A.R. 1985. Clinical epidemiology: The architecture of clinical research. Philadelphia: W.B. Saunders Company.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Feinstein, A.R. 1987. Clinimetrics. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Foucault, M. 1973. The birth of the clinic. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Gill, J.H. 2000. Michael Polanyi’s postmodern philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Wilczak, P.F. 1973. Faith, motive, and community: An interpretation of the philosophy of Michael Polanyi. Ph.D. thesis. Divinity School, University of Chicago.

  44. Henry, S.G., R.M. Zaner, and R.S. Dittu. 2007. Viewpoint: Moving beyond evidence-based medicine. Academic Medicine 82 (3): 292–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Cassell, E. 1985. Talking with patients. Volume 1. The theory of doctor-patient communication. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Wilensky, U. 1997. What is normal anyway? Therapy for epistemological anxiety. Educational Studies in Mathematics 33 (2): 171–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky. 1974. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science 185: 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hillel D. Braude.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Braude, H.D. Clinical intuition versus statistics: different modes of tacit knowledge in clinical epidemiology and evidence-based medicine. Theor Med Bioeth 30, 181–198 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-009-9106-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-009-9106-4

Keywords

Navigation