Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Content
    • Current Issue
    • Early Access
    • Multimedia
    • Podcast
    • Collections
    • Past Issues
    • Articles by Subject
    • Articles by Type
    • Supplements
    • Plain Language Summaries
    • Calls for Papers
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Reviewers
    • Job Seekers
    • Media
  • About
    • Annals of Family Medicine
    • Editorial Staff & Boards
    • Sponsoring Organizations
    • Copyrights & Permissions
    • Announcements
  • Engage
    • Engage
    • e-Letters (Comments)
    • Subscribe
    • Podcast
    • E-mail Alerts
    • Journal Club
    • RSS
    • Annals Forum (Archive)
  • Contact
    • Contact Us
  • Careers

User menu

  • My alerts

Search

  • Advanced search
Annals of Family Medicine
  • My alerts
Annals of Family Medicine

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Content
    • Current Issue
    • Early Access
    • Multimedia
    • Podcast
    • Collections
    • Past Issues
    • Articles by Subject
    • Articles by Type
    • Supplements
    • Plain Language Summaries
    • Calls for Papers
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Reviewers
    • Job Seekers
    • Media
  • About
    • Annals of Family Medicine
    • Editorial Staff & Boards
    • Sponsoring Organizations
    • Copyrights & Permissions
    • Announcements
  • Engage
    • Engage
    • e-Letters (Comments)
    • Subscribe
    • Podcast
    • E-mail Alerts
    • Journal Club
    • RSS
    • Annals Forum (Archive)
  • Contact
    • Contact Us
  • Careers
  • Follow annalsfm on Twitter
  • Visit annalsfm on Facebook
OtherReflections

Preventing Life-Sustaining Treatment by Default

Ursula K. Braun and Laurence B. McCullough
The Annals of Family Medicine May 2011, 9 (3) 250-256; DOI: https://doi.org/10.1370/afm.1227
Ursula K. Braun
MD, MPH
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Laurence B. McCullough
PhD
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Figures & Data
  • eLetters
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Abstract

Many physicians will at some point care for patients who will receive life-sustaining treatment by default, because there are no instructions available from the patient as to what kind of care is preferred, and because surrogates are likely to ask for everything to be done when they do not know a patient’s preferences. We use the methods of ethics informed by qualitative focus group research to identify 5 pathways to life-sustaining treatment by default originating with the patient’s preferred decision-making style: deciding for oneself or letting others decide. We emphasize preventing the ethically unwelcome outcome of life-sustaining treatment by default by increasing the frequency with which patients make clear decisions or clearly express their values and goals that they then communicate to physicians or surrogates.

  • Life-sustaining treatment by default
  • personal autonomy
  • end-of-life care
  • life support care
  • decision making
  • terminal care

INTRODUCTION

Life-sustaining treatment by default refers to receiving resuscitation, intubation, and mechanical ventilation; vasopressor and intensive care unit support; and administration of other life-sustaining treatments, such as artificial feeding or transfusions, in the absence of guidance from a seriously ill patient who either did not make decisions or did not, orally or in writing, clearly communicate his or her end-of-life decisions effectively to others. We describe different decision-making pathways taken by the patient that result in the administration of life-sustaining treatment by default.

Life-sustaining treatment by default is fraught with potential ethical conflict that can take a considerable and unwelcome biopsychosocial toll on patients, their surrogates, and clinicians.1–5 As a consequence, life-sustaining treatment by default can distort an organization’s culture by promoting attitudes of indifference toward patients receiving life-sustaining interventions for whom such interventions make little clinical sense, or by contributing to increased burnout in nursing staff caring for such patients. End-of-life decision making for patients who have not made or communicated their decisions can place an inordinate psychosocial and moral burden on surrogates, who may be struggling with a role they did not want or were unprepared to assume.3,6 When surrogates are unable to report a patient’s preferences, they can feel overwhelmed, which likely increases requests for everything to be done even when such interventions are thought to be futile.7 The ethical challenges of such requests are compounded when physicians label surrogates as difficult or irrational, leading to a breach of trust and problems in communication between clinicians and surrogates.4

The purpose of this article is to propose an ethically justified strategy8,9 to prevent life-sustaining treatment by default. We begin by identifying the concept of life-sustaining treatment as a trial of intervention and describe 3 factors that can combine to create life-sustaining treatment by default. We next explain the ethical concept of respect for the patient’s autonomy, which we then use to describe distinct pathways to life-sustaining treatment by default that originate in patient autonomy. We close by identifying preventive responses to the ethical challenge of life-sustaining treatment by default.

LIFE-SUSTAINING TREATMENT AS A TRIAL OF INTERVENTION

Life-sustaining treatment, which is often preceded by resuscitation, should be understood as a trial of intervention that can be stopped at any time if its goals no longer seem achievable.10–12 It is undertaken with the short-term goal of preventing imminent death. It is continued as long as it is reasonably expected, in evidence-based clinical judgment, to achieve its long-term goal: an acceptable clinical outcome. An acceptable clinical outcome can be defined from a clinical perspective (based on the ethical principle of beneficence) or the patient’s perspective (based on the ethical principle of respect for autonomy). A beneficence-based acceptable outcome means the preservation of at least some interactive capacity that is not overwhelmed by disease-related or iatrogenic morbidity, disability, pain, distress, or suffering.13 An autonomy-based acceptable outcome means an expected functional status that will result in a quality of life the patient is willing to accept.14

Physicians should make evidence-based clinical judgments about discontinuing life-sustaining treatment, especially (but not only) when the limits of such treatment have been reached—when it is no longer reasonably expected that the long-term goal can be achieved from the patient’s or the physician’s perspective. In both circumstances, physicians should offer the alternative of discontinuing treatment.

THREE FACTORS CONTRIBUTING TO LIFE-SUSTAINING TREATMENT BY DEFAULT

Three factors can combine to create life-sustaining treatment by default. First is the presumption of preserving life when a patient’s preferences are unknown or the prognosis is uncertain. Second is the request to do everything. Some patients do not clearly express and communicate their end-of-life decisions adequately. To compound matters, the patients’ surrogate decision makers may find their responsibility burdensome and stressful and cope by requesting everything be done to sustain life. Such requests can also stem from other factors, eg, a particular belief system (It’s in God’s hands—our duty is to try everything.). Third is the path of least resistance, which in response to requests to do everything, physicians fail to engage surrogates in thinking through the burdens and benefits of life-sustaining treatment, a process that can be time consuming.15 The result is administration of what we term life-sustaining treatment by default.

We emphasize that in the real world of uncertain prognosis, even if patients expressed clear preferences, clinical uncertainty or clinician discomfort with committing to a prognosis may lead to life-sustaining treatment. This outcome is not what we mean by life-sustaining treatment by default. For instance, a patient who suffered a massive stroke and has multiple preexisting comorbidities may be unlikely to wake up. The more time passes, the more the odds for a good outcome will likely diminish. Within this scenario, individual physicians will have different comfort zones where they can commit to a prognosis. In addition, patients sometimes do communicate their end-of-life decisions to others, but these decisions are not implemented. Failure to implement patients’ clearly expressed and effectively communicated decisions by clinicians or surrogates is not life-sustaining treatment by default, because it overrides patients’ preferences and violates their autonomy.

Of the 3 factors that can combine to create life-sustaining treatment by default—preserve life when the patient’s preferences are unknown or a prognosis is uncertain, request that physicians do everything to preserve life, and take the path of least resistance—the first is appropriate, but the second and third are candidates for change. Our focus is on the second, the patient-generated pathway, which we characterize as autonomy based.

RESPECT FOR THE PATIENT’S AUTONOMY

The foundation of preventive ethics in end-of-life decision making is respect for the patient’s autonomy. This ethical principle obliges health care professionals to acknowledge and respect the patient’s values and beliefs, to provide the patient with information requisite to make an informed choice, to prevent substantial control over or coercion in the patient’s decision-making process, and to implement the patient’s decision unless there is compelling ethical justification for not doing so.16

In the widely used textbook of bioethics, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, Beauchamp and Childress characterize the ethical principle of respect for autonomy as “enabling patients to overcome their sense of dependence and to achieve as much control as they desire.” 16 Culturally sensitive respect for autonomy means “[h]ealth professionals…should never assume that because a patient belongs to a particular community or culture, he or she affirms that community’s worldview and values.” 16 A key concept for translating respect for autonomy into clinical practice is the patient’s authority to make decisions, ie, the right to exercise a preferred level of control over the decision-making process and its outcome.16 The patient has the right to assert authority over decisions in the manner and to the extent that the patient selects 1 of 2 decision-making styles: retain all decision-making authority, or delegate that authority to others explicitly, implicitly, or by default. These choices can all be autonomous.

PATHWAYS TO LIFE-SUSTAINING TREATMENT BY DEFAULT

We presented findings from qualitative research that was based on focus groups of racially and ethnically diverse, seriously ill veterans and surrogate decision makers.3,17 We used inductive qualitative analysis to develop a conceptual model that identified pathways originating in 2 preferred decision-making styles, which we label in Figure 1⇓ as “I decide” and “let others decide.” From these 2 styles we found 5 pathways for end-of-life decision making that vary according to the underlying basis for the preferred decision-making style.

Figure 1.
  • Download figure
  • Open in new tab
  • Download powerpoint
Figure 1.

Pathways to life-sustaining treatment by default.

LST = life-sustaining treatment.

Our research suggests that patients who prefer to decide for themselves are motivated to either take responsibility for their own end-of-life decisions (Figure 1, A⇑) or avoid burdening others with having to make those decisions (Figure 1, B⇑). Patients whose decision-making style is to allow others to decide delegate that authority to others explicitly, implicitly, or by default.

Patients who explicitly authorize someone to act on their behalf (Figure 1, C⇑) are aware of who their legal surrogate would be; if the legal surrogate is not their preferred surrogate, they either officially name a person or tell their family whom they would like to appoint. These patients are highly likely to have discussed at least their general values with the preferred surrogate. Patients who implicitly authorize someone to act on their behalf (Figure 1, D⇑) know who their legal surrogate is but do not feel the need to appoint that person officially or to give that person specific instructions. They may have complete trust in that person’s judgment. Patients who by default allow someone to act on their behalf exercise their autonomy passively. Their unwillingness to broach the subject may reflect a willingness to accept any of their legal surrogate’s decisions or may be a form of denial, not wanting to explore what may happen when no longer able to make decisions (Figure 1, E⇑).

Included in Figure 1⇑ are some participants’ statements that we interpreted as representing these strategies. In Table 1⇓ we have drawn from our clinical practice examples of patients’ responding to palliative care consultations for each of these strategies.

View this table:
  • View inline
  • View popup
Table 1.

Five Scenarios of Patients’ Preferred Style of Delegating Decision-Making Authority

The 5 pathways (A through E) have 8 implementation strategies depending on whether the patients have clearly made and effectively communicated a decision about end-of-life care. Finally, these 8 implementation strategies can lead to 1 of 10 outcomes, 5 of which are life-sustaining treatment by default.

Of the life-sustaining treatment by default decision-making outcomes, number 5 (Figure 1⇑, bottom right), is intuitively the most obvious. Patients whose decision-making style is to let others decide and then to accept a legally assigned surrogate decision maker often have not made end-of-life decisions and thus have nothing to communicate. These patients can be understood as electing to let others decide by default, the minimally autonomous decision-making style. They do not exercise their autonomy as an explicit decision. Surrogates of such patients will have the least information about how to decide and thus may resort to life-sustaining treatment by default.

Number 4 in Figure 1⇑ illustrates an important aspect of life-sustaining treatment by default. Confidence in the legal surrogates’ judgment may allow patients to implicitly adopt the let-others-decide style. Surrogates, even without guidance by a patient, might know intuitively what a patient would have wanted; alternatively, the surrogates might be conflicted by having to make a genuine decision in the face of uncertainty and all its attending biopsychosocial burdens. Surrogates sometimes manage the burden by asking that everything be done to sustain life, resulting in life-sustaining treatment by default.5,7 Additionally, studies have shown that even when surrogates think they know what a patient would have wanted, patients would actually have chosen differently.18–24 In particular, surrogates who are chosen by patients specifically because they are personally close may have a hard time of letting go of their relationship; choosing against life-sustaining treatment may result in a patient’s death, thereby severing the relationship.23,24 Given that patients elect to trust the judgment of legal surrogates, however, such decisions would not violate the patients’ autonomy.

Life-sustaining treatment by default outcome 3 illustrates a scenario in which, despite the best intentions of giving guidance to someone entrusted with decision-making authority, patients may not have wholly communicated end-of-life preferences. Even if a patient formally authorized a surrogate by means of medical power of attorney, life-sustaining treatment by default could occur because the surrogate must make a genuine decision7 without sufficient guidance from the patient. Effective verbal communication of at least general values is the key to prevent life-sustaining treatment by default in this pathway.

The remaining 2 life-sustaining treatment by default outcomes, 1 and 2, originate in the decision-making style of deciding for oneself. Patients may explicitly adopt the I decide style and make a clear decision but not communicate it effectively to physicians or surrogates. These pathways expose an often insufficiently appreciated aspect of patient autonomy: regardless of whether a patient wants to take responsibility for his or her own decisions or does not want to burden others with end-of-life decisions, there is no guarantee against the provision of life-sustaining treatment by default, even if a patient does not want it.

Our conceptualization allows us to identify the common feature of the 5 distinct pathways to life-sustaining treatment by default: the failure of some patients to exercise their autonomy by explicitly and clearly communicating decisions or value-based preferences, either to their physicians or to their surrogate decision makers. This failure is compounded when patients lack legal surrogates and advance directives (about 5% of patients dying in intensive care units).25 Physicians should take what White et al describe as a facilitative role26 by advising all patients about the risks of life-sustaining treatment by default and encouraging them to express clear and preferred directives to their physicians, legal surrogates, or close friends who might act as their surrogates.

PREVENTING LIFE-SUSTAINING TREATMENT BY DEFAULT

Our reconceptualization of surrogate decision making proposes that, when surrogates request everything be done to sustain a patient’s life, they should be assumed to be burdened by a lack of input from the patient and experiencing high levels of stress.3 The surrogates’ decision-making process may be further complicated by the multiple sources surrogates draw on to make their own prognostic judgments.27

When patients communicate their preferences to surrogates, their role is to report the patients’ preferences to clinicians.7,27 Surrogates do not experience making such a report as making a decision, because there are no options to consider. For surrogates, reporting patients’ preferences is much less burdensome than the decision making required when patients’ preferences are unknown. The nuances and complexities of smaller day-to-day decisions are often laced with more uncertainty than big-picture decisions, such as DNAR (do not attempt resuscitation) status or placement of a PEG (percutaneous endoscopic gastrostomy) tube. Sometimes stated preferences do not readily translate to specific clinical decisions, such as whether antibiotics should be given for treatable pneumonia. Even so, such decisions will still be easier for surrogates who can confidently report treatment goals previously expressed by patients than for surrogates who had no guidance. The ability of surrogates to make a report, rather than a decision, should reduce the occurrence of life-sustaining treatment by default, and physicians should attempt to increase the frequency with which surrogates can make reports.

Preventing life-sustaining treatment by default outcomes 1, 2, and 3 build on pathways A, B, and C, in which patients have clearly made a decision. For these patients, physicians should strongly and, if necessary, repeatedly encourage patients to follow through by communicating their intentions clearly, orally or in writing, to their surrogates or to their physicians.

It will be more challenging to prevent life-sustaining treatment by default outcomes 4 and 5, because patients in pathways D and E do not have clear decisions to communicate. Physicians should encourage these patients to exercise their autonomy and express their decisions or general values to their surrogates.

The patient in Table 1⇑, scenario D, should be informed that although he has made a good start, counting on his wife to know what he wants risks life-sustaining treatment by default, and he should be encouraged to express his values and preferences to her so she can report them when he cannot. He also should be reminded that even though he trusts his wife to make the right choices, she might be burdened with making a decision without further guidance. End-of-life planning is often best accomplished with both the patient and the potential surrogate present. Such planning is not a single event but an ongoing process, and what is decided in one setting, eg, in the outpatient clinic, may need to be reevaluated and readdressed in another, eg, during an acute hospitalization. The patient in Table 1⇑, scenario E, requires stronger recommendations to communicate preferences to surrogates or physicians. Physicians should not hesitate to emphasize to a patient the risks of not dealing with the possibility of serious illness and thereby life-sustaining treatment by default.

Undertaking the above strategies may reduce the frequency with which patients elect life-sustaining treatment. We emphasize, however, that the primary goal of preventing life-sustaining treatment by default is not to alter the frequency with which life-sustaining treatment is authorized. Our goals are (1) to decrease the frequency of life-sustaining treatment by default, (2) to increase the frequency of clearly made and communicated decisions, and, therefore, (3) to enable more surrogates to make reports rather than burdensome decisions.

Our proposed strategies for preventing life-sustaining treatment by default have an important implication for the decades-old debate about which is more important, completing advance directives or securing medical power of attorney.28–33 Both are at risk of being unhelpful: the former may not express a clear decision, and the latter may only name a surrogate. Our emphasis is different and independent of the specific means by which patients elect to communicate their decisions; we emphasize encouraging and supporting patients to make clearly expressed decisions and values and then to communicate these decisions and values to their surrogates or physicians. Advance directives should be regarded as one, but not the only, tool patients can use to communicate their decisions effectively to others.

We have proposed important strategies for preventing life-sustaining treatment by default. Our strategies will help family members who act as surrogate decision makers to report the patient’s end-of-life preferences and thus reduce the biopsychosocial burdens of having to make decisions under conditions of uncertainty. Health care organizations can strengthen their organization’s professionalism by increasing the frequency with which end-of-life decisions implement respect for patients’ autonomy.

Footnotes

  • Conflicts of interest: authors report none.

  • Funding support: Drs Braun and McCullough were supported by the Department of Veterans Affairs, VA-HSR&D-IIR-02-224: A Culturally Sensitive Values-Guided Aid for End-of-life Decision Making. Dr Braun was also supported in part by funds from the Department of Health and Human Services (DSSH), Health Resources and Services Administration (HRSA) Bureau of Health Professions (BHPR), under Geriatric Academic Career Award 1 KO1 HP00074. Dr. Braun is staff physician at the Michael E. DeBakey Veterans Affairs Medical Center, Houston, Texas, and physician scientist at the Houston Department of Veterans Affairs, Veterans Health Administration, Health Services Research and Development Center of Excellence.

  • Disclaimer: The information or content and conclusions are those of the authors and should not be construed as the official position or policy of, nor should any endorsements be inferred by the DHHS, HRSA, BHPR, the VA, or the US Government.

  • Received for publication June 24, 2010.
  • Revision received October 26, 2010.
  • Accepted for publication November 23, 2010.
  • © 2011 Annals of Family Medicine, Inc.

REFERENCES

  1. ↵
    Field MJ, Cassel CK. Approaching Death: Improving Care at the End-of-Life. Washington, DC: National Academy Press; 1997.
  2. Lynn J, Goldstein NE. Advance care planning for fatal chronic illness: avoiding commonplace errors and unwarranted suffering. Ann Intern Med. 2003;138(10):812–818.
    OpenUrlPubMed
  3. ↵
    Braun UK, Beyth RJ, Ford ME, McCullough LB. Voices of African American, Caucasian, and Hispanic surrogates on the burdens of end-of-life decision making. J Gen Intern Med. 2008;23(3):267–274.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  4. ↵
    Braun UK, Beyth RJ, Ford ME, McCullough LB. Defining limits in care of terminally ill patients. BMJ. 2005;53(5):S137–S138.
    OpenUrl
  5. ↵
    Braun UK, Ford ME, Beyth RJ, McCullough LB. The physician’s professional role in end-of-life decision making: Voices of racially and ethnically diverse physicians. Patient Educ Counsel. 2009;Nov 28 [Epub ahead of print].
  6. ↵
    Azoulay E, Pochard F, Kentish-Barnes N, Chevret S, Aboab J, Adrie C, Annane D, et al; FAMIREA Study Group. Risk of post-traumatic stress symptoms in family members of intensive care unit patients. Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2005;171(9):987–994.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  7. ↵
    Braun UK, Naik AD, McCullough LB. Reconceptualizing surrogate decision making: reporting versus deciding for others. Ann Fam Med. 2009;7(3):249–253.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  8. ↵
    Chervenak FA, McCullough LB. Clinical guides to preventing ethical conflicts between pregnant women and their physicians. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 1990;162:303–307.
    OpenUrlPubMed
  9. ↵
    Forrow L, Arnold RM, Parker LS. Preventive ethics: expanding the horizons of clinical ethics. J Clin Ethics. 1993;4:287–294.
    OpenUrlPubMed
  10. ↵
    Lo B. Improving care near the end of life. Why is it so hard? JAMA. 1995;274(20):1634–1636.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  11. Miles SH, Koepp R, Weber EP. Advance end-of-life treatment planning. Arch Intern Med. 1996;156(10):1062–1068.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  12. ↵
    McCormick RA. To save or let die: the dilemma of modern medicine. JAMA. 1974;229(2):172–176.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  13. ↵
    Tomlinson T, Brody H. Ethics and communication in do-not-resuscitate orders. N Engl J Med. 1988;318(1):43–46.
    OpenUrlPubMed
  14. ↵
    Crippen D. Medical treatment for the terminally ill: the ‘risk of unacceptable badness’. Critical Care. 2005;9(4):317–318.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  15. ↵
    Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 6th ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
  16. ↵
    Brody BA. Life and Death Decision Making. New York: Oxford University Press, 1988.
  17. ↵
    Braun UK, McCullough LB, Ford ME, Espadas D, Beyth RJ. End-of-life care across race and ethnicities: voices of patients, surrogates, and physicians.J Am Geriatr Soc. 2005;53(5): S137–S138.
    OpenUrl
  18. ↵
    Shalowitz AI, Garrett-Mayer E, Wendler D. The accuracy of surrogate decision makers. Arch Intern Med. 2006;166:493–497.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  19. Hare J, Pratt C, Nelson C. Agreement between patients and their self-selected surrogates on difficult medical decisions. Arch Intern Med. 1992;152(5):1049–1054.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  20. Sulmasy DP, Terry PB, Weisman CS, et al. The accuracy of substituted judgments in patients with terminal diagnoses. Ann Intern Med. 1998;128:621–629.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  21. Sulmasy DP, Haller K, Terry PB. More talk, less paper: predicting the accuracy of substituted judgments. Am J Med. 1994 May;96(5):432–438.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  22. Suhl J, Simons P, Reedy T, Garrick T. Myth of substituted judgment. Surrogate decision making regarding life support is unreliable. Arch Intern Med. 1994 Jan 10;154(1):90–96.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  23. ↵
    Vig EK, Taylor JS, Starks H, Hopley EK, Fryer-Edwards K. Beyond substituted judgment: How surrogates navigate end-of-life decision-making. J Am Geriatr Soc, 2006;54(11):1688–1693.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  24. ↵
    Marks MA, Arkes HR. Patient and surrogate disagreement in end-of-life decisions: can surrogates accurately predict patients’ preferences? Med Decis Making. 2008;28(4):524–531.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  25. ↵
    White DB, Curtis JR, Wolf LE, et al. Life support for patients without a surrogate decision maker: Who decides? Ann Intern Med. 2007;147:34–40
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  26. ↵
    White DB, Malvar G, Karr J, Lo B, Curtis R. Expanding the paradigm of the physician’s role in surrogate decision-making: An empirically derived framework. Crit Care Med. 2010;38(3):743–750.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  27. ↵
    Boyd EA, Lo B, Evans LR, Malvar G, Apatira L, Luce JM, White DB. “It’s not just what the doctor tells me:” Factors that influence surrogate decision-makers’ perceptions of prognosis. Critical Care Medicine. 2010; 38(5): 1270–1275
    OpenUrlPubMed
  28. ↵
    Tolle SW, Tilden VP, Nelson CA, Dunn PM. A prospective study of the efficacy of the physician order form for life-sustaining treatment. J Am Geriatr Soc. 1998 Sep;46(9):1097–1102.
    OpenUrlPubMed
  29. Fagerlin A, Schneider CE. Enough. The failure of the living will. Hastings Cent Rep. 2004;34(2):30–42.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  30. Emanuel EJ. Living wills: are durable power of attorneys better? Hastings Cent Rep. 2004;34(6):5–6; author reply 6–7.
    OpenUrlPubMed
  31. Schneiderman LJ, Pearlman RA, Kaplan RM, Anderson JP, Rosenberg EM. Relationship of general advance directive instructions to specific life-sustaining treatment preferences in patients with serious illness. Arch Intern Med. 1992;152(10):2114–2122.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  32. Emanuel LL, Emanuel EJ. The medical directive: a new comprehensive advance care instrument. JAMA. 1989;261:3288–3293.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  33. ↵
    Teno JM, Licks S, Lynn J, et al. for the SUPPORT investigators. Do advance directives provide instructions that direct care? J Am Geriatr Soc, 1997;45:508–512.
    OpenUrlPubMed
PreviousNext
Back to top

In this issue

The Annals of Family Medicine: 9 (3)
The Annals of Family Medicine: 9 (3)
Vol. 9, Issue 3
1 May 2011
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author
  • In Brief
Print
Download PDF
Article Alerts
Sign In to Email Alerts with your Email Address
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on Annals of Family Medicine.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Preventing Life-Sustaining Treatment by Default
(Your Name) has sent you a message from Annals of Family Medicine
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the Annals of Family Medicine web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
16 + 1 =
Solve this simple math problem and enter the result. E.g. for 1+3, enter 4.
Citation Tools
Preventing Life-Sustaining Treatment by Default
Ursula K. Braun, Laurence B. McCullough
The Annals of Family Medicine May 2011, 9 (3) 250-256; DOI: 10.1370/afm.1227

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
Get Permissions
Share
Preventing Life-Sustaining Treatment by Default
Ursula K. Braun, Laurence B. McCullough
The Annals of Family Medicine May 2011, 9 (3) 250-256; DOI: 10.1370/afm.1227
Twitter logo Facebook logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Google Plus One

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Abstract
    • INTRODUCTION
    • LIFE-SUSTAINING TREATMENT AS A TRIAL OF INTERVENTION
    • THREE FACTORS CONTRIBUTING TO LIFE-SUSTAINING TREATMENT BY DEFAULT
    • RESPECT FOR THE PATIENT’S AUTONOMY
    • PATHWAYS TO LIFE-SUSTAINING TREATMENT BY DEFAULT
    • PREVENTING LIFE-SUSTAINING TREATMENT BY DEFAULT
    • Footnotes
    • REFERENCES
  • Figures & Data
  • eLetters
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF

Related Articles

  • PubMed
  • Google Scholar

Cited By...

  • In This Issue: Personalizing Health Care
  • Google Scholar

More in this TOC Section

  • When the Death of a Colleague Meets Academic Publishing: A Call for Compassion
  • Let’s Dare to Be Vulnerable: Crossing the Self-Disclosure Rubicon
  • The Soundtrack of a Clinic Day
Show more Reflections

Similar Articles

Subjects

  • Person groups:
    • Vulnerable populations
  • Methods:
    • Qualitative methods
  • Core values of primary care:
    • Personalized care
  • Other topics:
    • Ethics
    • Communication / decision making

Content

  • Current Issue
  • Past Issues
  • Early Access
  • Plain-Language Summaries
  • Multimedia
  • Podcast
  • Articles by Type
  • Articles by Subject
  • Supplements
  • Calls for Papers

Info for

  • Authors
  • Reviewers
  • Job Seekers
  • Media

Engage

  • E-mail Alerts
  • e-Letters (Comments)
  • RSS
  • Journal Club
  • Submit a Manuscript
  • Subscribe
  • Family Medicine Careers

About

  • About Us
  • Editorial Board & Staff
  • Sponsoring Organizations
  • Copyrights & Permissions
  • Contact Us
  • eLetter/Comments Policy

© 2025 Annals of Family Medicine